with security" was the ambition of the first major liberals. At the end of the 18th century and the 19th century, liberalism was already playing a progressive anti-feudal role, destroying the feudal remnants and opening the way to civil rights. For the liberals freedom alone was the basis of social stability. Following the traditions of A.Smith and considering himself a devout follower, Jean Battiste Sei idealised the system of free enterprise in the conviction that the market alone was sufficient to form balance. According to Sei's well-known law the crises of over-production are temporary and economic balance is equivalent to the existence of free market relations. All classical economic doctrines were developed on the basis of such fundamental conclusions. A century after the appearance of the economic views of Adam Smith (1776), the basis of the liberal idea - the very idea of free competition - was consigned to the graveyard. At the end of the 19th century with the appearance of large monopolies and the worsening crisis of capitalism, liberal doctrines began to lose their prestige and influence. Two world wars in the 20th century and the success of more radical and totalitarian regimes further limited their influence. Of course, during the first half of the 20th century, liberal ideas were still exerting influence on many thinkers and politicians. Some of them followed in the footsteps of William Jevens explaining all phenomena on the basis of the laws of subjective logic. Others by default became elementary apologists of the dominant bourgeois views and yet others became advocates of the views of Menger and Von Viser. All of them, however, were obliged to recognise that ideas of the automatic self-regulating and stabilising nature of the free market were mistaken. The world wars, colonial conflicts, imperialistic conflicts and totalitarianism dealt heavy body blows to the ideas of liberalism which lost much of its influence for a long time. Limited, reduced in influence and almost underground, the tradition of liberal thought continued into the 20th century. This was mainly due to the hard work of two "long-distance runners" of theoretical liberalism: Ludwig von Mizes and Friedrich von Haiek. Von Mizes in his "Human Activities" offers a series of ideas which contribute to the consolidation of the idea of individualism and individual freedoms. For Mizes the freedom of choice is at the basis of social development. He believes that economic theory and structure are entirely subjective. Every expansion of the structure of the state was regarded by Mizes and Hajek as an anomaly. In the opinion of Mizes the protection of the rights of hired labour limits freedom and in the long-term - the natural development of society. He was very critical of communism and in his work "Socialism" he brilliantly predicted many of the imperfections of the "socialist experiment". In the 19th century Liberalism was a strongly progressive science. It destroyed the foundations of absolutism and opened the way to civil and political freedoms. It was the theoretical crown of laurels of the modern age and an expression of the Third Civilisation. Liberalism was the hope of the ordinary citizen, the bourgeois, the craftsman, the small and medium scale land owner. It was the ideology of the struggle against the "unjustified privileges" of the aristocrats and monarchs, the ideology of those who guarantee the power of the bourgeois above the other members of society. There is no doubt that in the 19th century one particular rule was valid - the more widespread the ideas of liberalism, the greater the authority of the bourgeois class. Liberalism was a victim of its own success and gave birth to its own antipathy - Marxism. Someone had to defend the interests of hired labour. Someone had to bring attention to the plight of a new repressed class with its own role and problems in society. The freedom of some had turned into the lack of freedom of others. This was the law of the Third Civilisation, of the level of progress that had been reached at that moment in the development of mankind. The collapse of the feudal societies had given birth to the bourgeoisie and the proletariate and the ideological doctrines which corresponded to their interests. Marxism developed as a new wave of intellectual thought but soon turned into a class doctrine. It was based on the idea of the value manufacturing output and the capitalist accumulation of wealth which arises from it. Marx was an undisputed theoretician and thinker. He not only developed the ideas of Smith but turned them in a completely new direction. While J.B. Sei and John Stuart Mill absolutised the idea of free enterprise and "Laissez Faire" economics, Marx took things in a new direction. He looked for the contradictions inherent in the free market and "proved" that sooner or later they would lead to monopolism, class conflicts and the objective transformation of private ownership into public ownership. While Sei and his followers promoted the capitalism of the 19th century and considered it as an eternal and balanced system, Marx, on the other hand, described its vices and called for the replacement of this society with a more just system. At the root of the theory of the value of labour, he emphasised that one part of society unjustly exploited the other part in contradiction with the natural rights of man. The struggle for added value, in the opinion of Marx, was at the root of class division between the bourgeoisie and the proletariate. Here Marx is in his role as a theoretician and political revolutionary. He undoubtedly believed that at some time during the process of capitalist accumulation, the "Laissez Faire" formula would collapse since competition would lead to centralisation, monopolisation and eventually, political and class conflicts. Marx, and later Lenin, frequently reiterated that monopolisation was a logical consequence of competition. These conclusions by Marx were indisputedy true of the 19th century and a significant part of the 20th. In Chapter 23 of the first volume of "Das Kapital", Marx comes to his most significant theoretical conclusion. For years to come it was to serve the interests of Lenin and later Stalin as the keystone of "state socialism". He believed that the processes of natural accumulation of industrial capital would not only lead to high levels of concentration but also objective and inevitable centralisation which would kill the ideas of "Laissez Faire" and would set preconditions for the transfer of private ownership to the state. "In a given area", writes Marx, "centralisation will attain its extreme limit when all the capital invested in it merge into a single capital. In a given society, this limit will be attained only when the entire social capital is united in the hands of a single, individual capitalist or a single group of capitalists."[27] This leads to the basis thesis which was to be further developed by Lenin - historical development and progress gradually lead to the increase in the level of socialisation, in the concentration and centralisation of production. This conclusion and the conclusion on the historical role of the working class and its rights to added value (logically - to the sum of social wealth) are the keystones of Marxist theory. The main conclusion was that private ownership would be destroyed in order to concede its place to public ownership. Later on the followers of Marx were to become divided over this issue. Kaustski considered that the priority of Marxist thought was that the capitalist society would reform itself and that parliamentary democracy would stimulate such a process. At the other extreme Lenin and his followers, motivated by the dramatic situation in semi-feudal Russia were to raise the flag of the revolutionary struggle for the rights of the poor in the belief that before capitalism could be transformed into anything else, inter-imperialistic conflicts would lead to its death and the inevitable world victory of the proletariate. This was the main reason why the Marxist tradition divided at the beginning of the 20th century into two major movements - social democracy and communism. In both cases, however, they share the same political doctrines and common theoretical views. Both communism and world social democracy in the 20th century placed the emphasis on the protection of the rights of the workers and the socially weak strata of the population and at the same time the strong regulatory role of the state. Under communism the role was taken to absurd extreme via the total nationalisation of production. In social-democracy the role of the state was reduced to its "natural" dimensions defined by the need for it to protect the interests of the socially weak. In 1989-1991 with the collapse of the Eastern European totalitarian structures Marxism suffered a terrible blow. Of course, it is hardly possible to identify Eastern European totalitarianism with Marxism, Marxism with Stalinism, Maoism or Potism. Marx was complex and occasionally even contradictory but his name will remain forever in the annals of the history of economic and social disciplines. His conclusions canbe disputed, and only some of them are valid for the period in which he lived. Others arouse our admiration even today. Amongst the latter, I would cite his philosophical ideas of dialecticism and analyses of market prices and competition. Toffler is correct when he says that to ignore the writings of Marx today is tantamount to being semi-literate. In my book, I do not reject Marx as a thinker, but I do reject the practical implementation of his ideas and their politicisation and transformation into dogma. The globalisation of the world, the universal crisis of the two bloc system and the appearance of new technology struck Marxist political practice a blow to the heart. The total nationalisation of society was in fact in divergence with the realities of world development. The idea that capitalist accumulation would lead to a unified, centralised society, to a single system of production for all workers and to a global proletarian state were mistaken. The first reason for this was because the consolidation of the proletarian state as a rule was achieved via violence and secondly, because such views lead to the repression of individual rights and freedoms and the limitation of human creativity. The Marxist intellectual tradition lost its influence to new technologies and social developments in the 1970's and 1980's which were at odds with the structures of state property. The West had begun to overcome class contradictions and they had reached entirely new levels of social development. Modern generations are now witnessing the disappearance of the traditional working class, the appearance of new social groups and new social structures. In actual fact both the politically charged "intellectual discoveries" of Karl Marx - the theory of added value and the universal law on capitalist accumulation - have been overtaken by history. Neither his views on expropriation by expropriators, nor the struggles of the world proletariate correspond to what is happening in the world at the moment. This does not mean that the Marxist intellectual tradition has to be forgotten or rejected. It has played an essential role in the development of the world during a long period of its development. Marx correctly predicted that the period of free competition would not last long and that it would lead to imperialism and the increase in inter-imperialist conflicts. Marxism became a powerful gravitational force for many people during the second half of the 19th century and the first half of the 20th since it offered a true reflection of the tragic position of workers during this period and defended their interests. "State socialism" as it was called was the transitional type of social progress combined with exalted utopian views and violent methods for attaining them. On the other hand state socialism guaranteed social security (work, wages and a basic standard of living) for millions of people. There is no other reasonable way to describe the popularity of these teachings and its influence throughout a large part of the world's populations in the 19th and 20th century. The Western European social democratic version of Marxism played a role as a balancing force, a bridge between the different classes. In Eastern Europe, Asia and Africa it was a series of generally unsuccessful experiments. The total nationalisation of Stalin in the 1930's, reformed by Khrushchev and supported by Brezhnev, the "great leap forward" of Mao Tse Tung at the end of the 1950's and the senseless purges of Pol Pot were all justified under the banner of Marxist ideas and the struggle for a global communist future. The historical fate of Marxism reveals one important truth. When a teaching imposes itself mechanically on different cultures and traditions or when it used simply as a banner, it automatically turns into dogma. Every attempt at reform in the 1970's and 1980's in Eastern Europe was justified with quotes from Marx and Lenin and supporting quotations from the works of the great leaders could always be found even in the most contradictory situation. This was absurd. We were obliged at every turn to refer to the classic works. Marxism lost its authority and was turned into an compulsory state religion. At first glance with the collapse of the totalitarian regimes in Eastern Europe liberalism seemed to remain the only gravitational force for the development of mankind, with no recognition of gratitude to Marx or Lenin. The semi-statism of the world's social democrats is in crisis, neo-Keynesianism is under pressure from market expansion in the open world and modern communications seem to be whispering, "less state intervention, more freedom". The followers of Mizes and Von Hajek hastily declared after the death of Marxism that there is nothing left but liberalism. This illusory triumph found its fullest expression in the work of F.Fukoyama, "The End of History". In the style of Sei's eternal doctrines of the "eternal" market balancing force, Fukoyama declared the intransigent superiority of liberal ideas and subsequently the end of history. He seems to believe that the market, individualism and the private entrepreneur are the only quantifiable categories. For Hegel and now Fukoyama, the "end of history" is the fear of the unfathomable great future, something which needs to be defined now, despite the fact that by rights it belongs to future generations. Hegel's long-dreamed-of modern world will appear at the end of history in the same way as Fukoyama asserts that the most perfect system is liberal democracy and that it will bring with it the "last man" and the "end of history". What I cannot accept in these concepts is that history and its philosophy have a perceivable end and that social schemes and doctrines can be written in stone for eternity. I prefer to believe that history is cyclical and that its follows the laws of the great natural systems of the universe. We still know too little, to be able to give an adequate answer to this question. We know so little about our own planet and about the galaxies which surround it and especially the connection between this and the history of mankind. Despite the poverty of human knowledge it is clear that there is no proof of the inevitable end of mankind and earthly nature. The explanation seems to suggest that the end of history will be accompanied by the universal domination of liberalism. The modern world is colourful and diverse enough to support the belief that a traditional ideology can transform itself in a dominant philosophy. Even the elementary claims that after the collapse of Eastern European totalitarianism and "a short, sharp shock" liberal doctrines would win the hearts and minds of Russians, Bulgarians, Poles or Slovaks were hasty. This did not take place and because of the inherited economic and cultural realities clearly will not. However, are the Eastern countries of Japan, South Korea or China symbols of liberal democracies? Will the countries of Latin America, Asia and Africa be able to develop in this way? The trends prevalent at the moment in Western Europe and the USA give no grounds for such "liberal" optimism. Modern liberal doctrines do not correspond to the most significant modern processes of globalisation, socialisation or the opening-up of countries and the mutual interaction of different cultures. The very nature of private property has changed. It is more socialised and integrated than at any other time. Humanity is faced with completely new problems which fall outside the domain of liberalism. Today's global world is disproportionately developed and traditional liberalism will hardly be able to change this. If we apply its traditional ideology universally, the world economy will mutate even further. The wealthy countries will become even more wealthy and the poor even poorer. The God of wealth for some will be at the same time the God of poverty for others, leading to a renewal of liberalism and a revitalisation of some new form of Marxism and defender of the socially weak. Today practically no-one has any doubts that classical liberal thought is part of the glorious past. There is, however, another hypothesis that after the collapse of totalitarian socialism liberalism will be born again. Some modern liberals assert that Ronald Reagan and Margaret Thatcher with their typically liberal policies brought about the collapse of communism.[28] Others consider that neo-liberalism is but a rationalist deviation in the era of violence, typical of this century. "However, if there is any kind of hope for the future of freedom", wrote John Grey in 1986, " then it is hidden in the fact that towards the end of century of political insanity, we are becoming witnesses of a return to the wisdom of the great theorists of liberalism."[29] With respect for these views, I would, all the same, like to express my view that history never repeats itself. We must accept the market, human rights, individual freedom and so on, but will this alone solve the problems of the modern world or provide a solution to the challenges with which we are faced? On their own these liberal doctrines are inadequate for the processes of globalisation. They will as a matter of course lead to the development of a number of social conflicts for a relatively long time to come. They will lead to a deformation of world development and a consolidation of the division of humanity into the rich and the poor. This will create a new reaction in the poorer countries and the appearance of new utopias and local wars. A century ago liberalism very rapidly changed from a doctrine of spiritual freedom into a doctrine of the rich. Today it is hardly able to return freedom to the poor, or the freedom taken away by the electronic media. In the context of the global world liberal doctrines are rather a refuge for those who want to expand their historical advantages and the historical lead they have over the others and to dominate the world. The greatest danger in the context of the global world is that liberalism will be transformed into a bridge for the domination of cultures leading to the disappearance of national traditions and entire peoples. In combination with globalisation market liberalism might easily mutate into cultural elitism. If we follow the ideological concept of liberalism in the context of the global world we will be faced with the dangers mentioned in the previous chapter - chaos and disorder, nationalist and ethnic crises, the reactions of the poor and all the manifestations of the universal crisis of the Third Civilisation. Both historically and currently the idea of liberalism is different from the present state of the world. The worst thing is that with such ideas we will primitivise world development and we will turn globalisation into a bridge for the mechanical imposition of one culture onto another. In practice this means the Americanisation of Russia, the Germanisation of the Czech Republic and Hungary and China and India simultaneously to imitate the United States and the United Kingdom and so on. Least of all we want to resemble ourselves. The world can only lose out and become ashamed of itself. Of course, it would be absurd and superfluous to ignore the strengths of liberal theories. Freedom, human rights, private initiative and property are things which we have inherited through the centuries and which we will take with us into the future. The problem is, however, that in the modern world this is far from enough. Neither liberalism nor Marxism-Leninism can explain the modern processes of world integration, the reduction of the role of national states, the appearance and the principles of the global world, mutual interaction of cultures in the context of internationalisation. These two doctrines appeared during the industrial era, in the conditions of strong class division and inequality. They served the needs of the Third Civilisation with their inherent structures - nations and nation states. Their basic laws and categories were connected to the problems faced by mankind during the 19th and 20th century. Today, however, all this has changed as a result of modern technological processes, as a result of modern social structures and the evolution of ownership. Marx's working class does not exist, there is no class hegemony, proletarian revolutions are senseless. At the same time the ideal private owner in the conditions of the intermingling of millions of private activities and the increase in the dependence of each individual does not exist. Just like the new technologies did not find their place within the shell of state bureaucratic "socialist" governments, in the same way the socialisation of private property and the globalisation of the world have destroyed the basic values of liberalism. It is true that each of these doctrines can adapt and take on board new ideas. However, this would be a perpetration ofviolence against history and academic morals. Such attempts are being carried out at the moment stemming from the political ambitions and inherited from the past but as a rule they serve only to delay the reform process. Their hypocrycy will be quickly perceived. In the early period of my academic research I also allowed myself to indulge in such illusions attempting to imagine the ideas of sweeping reform in Eastern Europe as the revitalisation of socialism. At that time this was about as far as we were allowed to go. Today, when we are relatively free it would much more honest to confess that the time of ready-made ideas has long since passed. New generations have the right to their own ideas and the logical progress of history does not mean the acceptance of old cliches. Neither Marxism-Leninism can be successfully adapted to individualism, the market or private enterprise, nor can liberalism accept within its own systems the international and internal associations created by new communications. It is equally absurd to believe that ideological doctrines can be based on a priori class status - theories about capitalists, theories about workers and peasants. This approach was suitable in the 19th and 20th centuries when the integration of society was at a much lower level and social stratification was much more acute and significant. I expect political liberals and "socialist" movements to begin to adapt to the new realities. It is sometimes amusing that those who call themselves socialist may carry out anti-socialist politics in support of the major monopolies. There may even be liberals and conservatives who preach politics in the name of the people and social economic ideas. The comedy of make-up and disguise will continue for another 10-15 years and maybe more. We will hear more and more frequently that the changes have only served to confirm the ideas of Karl Marx and L.Von Mizes. This is, however, to insult these two great thinkers. This is why I cannot announce the end of Marxism or liberalism, but can only give forewarning that the end will come - about that there can be no doubt. History teaches us that new eras give rise to new ideas. We are now entering such an era. 2 A RETURN TO THE ROOTS OR THE MAIN THESIS The theory and the practice of liberalism stresses the absolutism of the individual and private property and hence the monopoly of power of the strong over the weak. Marxism-Leninism created the total monopoly of the state by absolutising socialisation and state ownership. I have come to the conclusion that neither socialisation not autonomisation can be achieved individually or absolutely... I n 1982 when I was writing my doctoral dissertation, I wanted to find an answer to the question, "Does state socialism justifiably exist?" Why were its ideas dominant at that time in a number of countries including Bulgaria? According to Lenin, "State socialism is based on the socialisation of capitalist production."[30] By the world "socialisation" Marx, Engels and Lenin meant the development of the social character of autonomous social processes. In their opinion humanity was progressing logically from individual to larger mass forms of production, passing through the stages of primitive labour to slave owning and feudal manufacturing processes, the development of the factory eventually to reach the large scale monopolies. Subsequently Marxism-Leninism states that the next step in socialisation after monopolies is the creation of social ownership or property controlled by the state itself. At first glance, this might appear logical: in the stages of its progress, humanity passes from primitive individual production to enormous factories and eventually state control within the framework of the entire society. Marx and Lenin frequently come back to this emphasising that private property is too limiting for the new productive forces and that it gives rise to wars and violence subsequently conceding its position to state control. There is no difference in principle here between Marx, Lenin, Stalin, Trotski or Mao Tse Tung. They all saw socialisation as a global process, the basis and pre-condition for the establishment of a world communist society, of a "single factory for all workers and peasants" (Lenin). Taking this as the basis and putting to one side (briefly) the Marxist thesis of the decay of the state, the pioneer politicians of state socialism unified life and put up barriers to motivation and the progress of people. In order to analyse this process, we can take the most simple example - the example of natural organisms. Organic cells do not only grow when they develop (unless they are cancerous) but divide and become autonomous. If they separate from the main body of cells they die. If larger natural systems attack their independent development, the cells die or cease to exist in the same form. All growth of organisms in nature is associated with autonomous development. The other option is decay and inevitable death. Similarly, if socialisation and centralisation are viewed as a unilateral process, they (like cancer cells) will automatically lead to the mutation of the system. It is true that each subsequent stage of human development leads to the greater homogeneity of human civilisation. However, if this thesis is not further developed, it become transformed into a rejection of its own self. For Stalin and his followers, for Mao and Pol Pot progress meant socialisation, equal to unification, military discipline and universal obedience to superiors. This was the very basis for the doctrine of state socialism and the gradual unification of society. In the 1920's and 1930's the USSR and in the 1950's the countries of Eastern Europe underwent the total nationalisation of their industry and agriculture. There was a belief in the theory that via state regulated homogeneity the differences between village and town, intellectual and physical work and classes would disappear and that this would be the basis for subsequent "social homogeneity" and "nationalisation". This was the model for state socialism. It meant death for individual activities, creativity and motivation. To a lesser extent it suffocated the diversity of social life. Naturally it also delayed and in certain circumstances halted social development. The most important element in my understanding of this matter is that integration (socialisation) and autonomation are not mutually exclusive but a pair of categories which develop in parallel and are mutually conditioned. The same can also be said of other pairs of processes such as globalisation and localisation, integration and disintegration, collectivisation and individualisation, massification and demassification etc.. However paradoxical this might appear at first glance, I believe that these pairs of processes have developed in parallel and not to the detriment of one another. Of course, the phases of socialisation and autonomation, unification and collapse cannot appear simultaneously. At each stage in the development of human history the socialisation of production replaces a particular level of autonomy and in its turn gives way to another. The slave owning state socialised the labour of thousands of slaves and gradually within the very heart of the system new centres of autonomy began to appear setting the preconditions for the appearances of colonies and the early stages of feudalism. Capitalism destroyed the feudal divisions but in its place a new type of autonomy appeared. However hard it tried to suppress autonomy, the totalitarian regimes could not destroy the autonomy of social groups and individual people were eventually to destroy the monopoly of power. Let us take the elementary example of the single division of labour. The idea of the socialisation of labour is based on the fact that the individual units of labour complement each other within the processes of the creation of a final product. Craftsmen are divided from the agricultural worker, the trader from the craftsman etc.. On the one hand they all are dependent on each other but on the other (and this is particulary important) they achieve greater professional autonomy and greater freedom of action. Similar processes develop in relation to the forms of unified labour - certain economic units are absorbed up by others while at the same time in the process of capital accumulation yet others become more powerful and more independent. At a certain stage in their development they divide into individual autonomous structures. Large companies as General Motors for example transfer a number of their activities to smaller independent companies. Each larger production unit is then obliged to autonomise its internal departments. Moreover, the more developed and bigger the unit is, the greater the autonomy of its component parts. This process is confirmed by the decentralisation of management in transnational corporations. In general the growth of the whole cannot help but bring with it the growth of its individual parts. The increased process of integration will at a certain stage in its development lead to division and a certain level of autonomisation. Thus, the growth in socialisation does not lead to the death of autonomisation but to its reproduction and change in its forms. The growth in integration leads to another type of disintegration, globalisation and another type of localisation etc.. Each human activity is a form of accumulation. On the one hand the process of accumulation as both a material and spiritual process leads simultaneously to two effects: firstly, it concentrates the material and social forces in one area making them socially and naturally more independent and autonomous, secondly, this accumulation leads to millions of new types of manufacturing, economic and social links between human communities, countries and continents. If we take the level of autonomy of individual structural units, then in certain cases their levels of autonomy increase, others decrease and disappear while yet others appear and continue to develop. In general terms the socialisation and autonomisation of structures are linked by a complex series of relations which complement each other at the same time. The main element is that during the development of the historical processes they follow a common line of development and growth. Moreover, it is clear that neither individualism nor collectivism can of their own accounts express the richness of human interdependence. Separated from one another, these categories create deformation. Pure individualism without any idea of the community is antipathetical to the idea of the objective integrational processes while forced collectivism kills diversity and initiative. By the same logic, the state socialist collective societies limit individualism and creativity and delay progress. I am convinced that history will lead us to a combination of the elements of the individual and the social: the integration of human activities unify a series of autonomous production processes, countries and peoples making the world more united and more mutually dependent. At the same time there will be growth in the social role of the individual, autonomous groups and ethnic communities. Material accumulation and the growth in wealth available to civilisations makes man wealthier better informed and consequently freer and more independent. The more humanity develops the more this trend will continue. It will be more difficult to "entrap" such a person within the monopolistic structures of managed societies. I, therefore, believe that in global terms it is possible to speak of the disintegration of historical distances between the individual (private relations) and the collective (public relations). History has indisputedly shown that objective integrational processes are ineffective without some form of administrative compulsion. The higher the level of civilisation within society the greater the harmony between the individual and society. 3 MAIN CONCLUSIONS AND A MESSAGE TO A.TOFFLER Since the 1960's the technological basis of world manufacturing has changed out of all recognition. So much new technology has entered every day life that social relations have also changed. One of the best modern philosophers, A.Toffler, maintains that new technology leads to the emassification of production. My belief is that the effect is somewhat different. I believe that it gives rise to the parallel processes of integration and disintegration, massification and demassification and that it is this dual effect which has influenced the world in this extraordinary way. T he existence of a dialectic link between integration anddisintegration, globalisation and localisation can be summed upin three basic conclusions. The first conclusion is that these pairs of categories of historical development are not antipathies but develop in parallel and are mutually conditioned. This concept is equivalent to the rejection of utopian liberal theories of absolute independence and the "purity" of private ownership. However, this is also a rejection of the notions of a future society as a world without individualism, internal autonomy, local characteristics and without economic, political and cultural diversity. The second conclusion is that socialisation, or integration is not the same is nationalisation or centralisation. If this was a unilateral process (the persistent unification of autonomous units) then this concentration would lead to centralisation and would lead to the growth in nationalisation. The view that autonomisation goes hand in hand with socialisation means that socialisation is above all a "horizontal" process based on man, the market and private property. Consequently centralisation has certain permissible limits beyond which it is ineffective and provokes reactionary processes. The theoretical conception of the state in the modern world has changed significantly. It is clear that in modern conditions the borders of the state have undergone considerable changes. The greater the level of development on the one hand, the more civic society will be absorbed up by the state - and vice versa. My third conclusion[31] is that from an international point of view, socialisation (integration) gives rise to new phenomena connected firstly with globalisation and secondly with the appearance of increased local autonomy and localisation. On the one hand, new communications unite humanity, on the other hand they create national and ethnic self-confidence leading to the struggle for the survival of nations and cultures as a reaction to cultural imperialism. Liberalism and Marxism-Leninism are unable to provide explanations for the new realities. Liberal doctrines emphasise individualism, personal freedom, while Marxism places the emphasis on class and collectivism. When liberalism and Marxism appeared on the historical stage, their one dimensional nature was to a certain extent entirely understandable. The liberals defended the rights of free, private entrepreneurs while the Marxists defended the working class and the poor. The level of stratification within civilised societies was so clear and so developed that such doctrines were inevitable. They were a historical necessity and their mark in history. It will be interesting to see whether these conclusions will be confirmed by the modern technological revolution which is apparently taking shape at the moment and which will continue to shape the face of the world for some time to come. In a number of his books the famous American philosopher and futurologist, A.Toffler, concludes that new technologies lead to the demassification of production. "At the present moment", he writes, "We are passing from an economy of mass production and mass consumption to what I would call "the demassed economy".[32]" In the opinion of the great American futurologist, large scale mass production will be replaced by individualised or small scale production. Identical components will be assembled in more and more individualised end products. I wanted to draw attention to this thesis not because it is original but rather that it has lead to the revival of the illusion that liberalism and free trade will triumph. The basic idea of Toffler is that the modern technological revolution will return the demassification of production as the leading form of economic relations which will in turn mean the collapse of the large trans-nationals corporations or at least the reduction of their role, the domination of the small and medium scale sector and the rebirth of free competition